Summer 2014 (28.2) Review

Fairness in Practice: A Social Contract for a Global Economy by Aaron James

Fairness in Practice: A Social Contract for a Global Economy, Aaron James (New York: Oxford University Press, 2012), 380 pp., $74 cloth.

We are all familiar with the claim that the rules of the World Trade Organization (WTO) are unjust or otherwise objectionable. Yet this claim faces substantial hurdles in motivating corrective action. Most significantly, wealthy states face political pressures against moderating their bargaining positions. But this is not the only problem. First, there remains the suspicion that these rules are not, in fact, objectionable, or that they are only mildly so—perhaps “bad” but not “unjust.” After all, no country is forced to be subject to them; the WTO is a voluntary institution. Second, we still have to determine what rules would be just. Is it really the job of the WTO to compensate for inherent inequalities between countries? In this book, the first philosophical work devoted exclusively to “fair trade,” Aaron James seeks to combat the second of these challenges directly. In doing so, he also combats the first.

James argues for WTO concessions for developing countries from a “practice-dependent” perspective—a perspective from which the character of a social practice shapes the moral requirements that apply to it (pp. 25–31)—and he devotes the first third of the book to elucidating the “social practice of mutual reliance by societies on common markets” (p. x). Political economists commonly model the relevant circumstances as a Prisoner’s Dilemma. In this model, each state is best served by raising trade barriers—whether to influence the terms of trade, limit domestic inequality, protect infant industries, or placate domestic interests —regardless of what others do. The problem is that by raising such barriers every state is thereby worse off than if all states simply refrained from protectionism. The role of a trade regime, then, is to enable an integrated order by threatening to punish protectionism.

By contrast, James puts issues of uncertainty and risk up front. The basic problem is that even if all states were willing to base their trade-policy choices on what it is collectively rational to do—and eschew the cheating that fuels the Prisoner’s Dilemma even absent the threat of punishment—market integration would still be impeded if states wrongly believed that others were motivated to cheat. In the absence of assurance that others are similarly inspired, even the ethically motivated state’s best strategy is to resist market integration preemptively—that is, to preempt being cheated on by others (p. 106). (Although James thinks that this dynamic is best represented by Rousseau’s Stag Hunt game, arguably Robert Jervis’s Spiral Model—a version of the Security Dilemma beloved of international relations theorists—is more apt.) Any degree of market integration absent a regime, therefore, is already evidence of a social practice: one in which states risk the goodwill of others and provide assurance of their own goodwill in doing so.

James emphasizes this alternative game for at least two reasons. First, he wants to stress that the normative principles he ultimately defends would be applicable even if there was no regime (p. 54). Second, he wants to respond to the realist who thinks that no state can be under an obligation to moderate its bargaining stance absent assurance that others will do likewise. His view seems to be that the mere fact that countries have taken a risk in making themselves dependent on foreign markets in the first place is assurance enough on this score (p. 88).

It is also possible that James downplays the Prisoner’s Dilemma to highlight distributional concerns. It is sometimes thought that the Prisoner’s Dilemma demonstrates that there is an obligation to act as collective rationality demands—in order to accord with the categorical imperative or to avoid free-riding. The problem is that this thought appears to vindicate the WTO’s current rules—indeed, even if no country had signed up to them! Yet even if there is an obligation to act on some principles that, if all acted on them, all would gain, there remains the question of how gains are to be distributed, and therefore which particular principles should be adopted.

In the middle third of the book, James defends those principles that he thinks should guide WTO deliberations. His first principle (“Collective Due Care”) requires that no person be worse off than if their society remained autarkic (pp. 204–19), while his second (“International Relative Gains”) requires that each state achieve an equal increase in income per capita as a result of trade integration (pp. 221–26). James defends International Relative Gains on the basis that all countries enter the trade order with the same aim—augmenting national income—and play a structurally similar role in sustaining it.

One virtue of his view is that it provides a basis on which to criticize the WTO without implying that it ought to be some sort of charitable organization—one charged with addressing even those inequalities that would exist absent globalization. An additional merit is that he provides a basis on which to justify a departure from the WTO’s current pillars—namely, reciprocity and most-favored-nation treatment—that is not merely ad hoc. If ensuring that poorer countries gain equally requires the unilateral opening of Northern markets (in agriculture and textiles, for instance) or trade-policy discrimination (against imports that do not originate in poorer countries, perhaps), so be it.

Finally, James offers us his third principle (“Domestic Relative Gains”), which requires that co-citizens gain equally from their country’s trade integration (pp. 219–21). As the gains of trade arise from national specialization (for example, according to comparative advantage), James argues that they are returns over which no individual has a privileged claim. While there is undoubtedly something to his argument, the resulting principle seems rather demanding. Indeed, aren’t there cases where there is cause to celebrate even a domestic distribution of trade gains that departs so far from equality as to violate Collective Due Care as well: namely, when trade integration undermines the disproportionate wealth and power that can come with captive markets?

In the last third of the book, James turns to some topics for which mutual market reliance is clearly relevant, but which are less comfortably categorized under “trade.” On short-term capital flows, he argues from an analogy involving a bio-agent—one that is economically advantageous but carries with it a significant risk of causing a highly contagious disease—for a collective regime of capital controls intended to limit financial crises. On intellectual property and worker exploitation, he argues from his three principles. Thus, intellectual property “theft” is not objectionable as long as it enables poorer countries to get closer to an equal increase in income per capita, even if it deprives corporations of revenues they would otherwise reap. And seemingly inequitable wages in developing countries represent an injustice only if they are low because WTO rules do not allow those countries to achieve sufficient growth or sustain redistributive institutions domestically. James maintains that the entitlements of private actors are derivative because it is states that legitimately determine who is even in a position to trade with whom across borders.

In defending International Relative Gains, James directly combats alternative views, including that trade gains should fall in whatever way they happen to given the terms of private contracts in globalized markets (pp. 166–67; 174–79), and that WTO rules should represent a rational solution to bargaining between self-interested states (pp. 170–74; 227–28). Perhaps more valuable, though, is a thread of reasoning throughout that combats the first of our hurdles to action.Given the size of the WTO, and the fact that it demands a “single undertaking” (one set of rules for all), countries do not have a sufficiently attractive alternative besides membership. Consequently, the WTO is only voluntary in a weak sense, and its rules might be seriously objectionable despite the nominal assent of states.

By way of conclusion, it is worth noting that evaluating the global economy with any degree of rigor is not something that can be accomplished without traversing traditional academic boundaries. Thankfully, though, Fairness in Practice is a model of interdisciplinary scholarship. By bringing political economy, international relations, and development economics into conversation with moral philosophy, James has made a critical contribution to the debate over the ethics of globalization.

—SIMON COTTON

Simon Cotton is a postdoctoral research associate in values and public policy at Princeton University.

More in this issue

Summer 2014 (28.2) Essay

Why Human Rights Are Called Human Rights

No one can engage in commerce when deprived of liberty or autonomy. No one can create or imagine or love when consumed by fear. We ...

Summer 2014 (28.2) Essay

The Future of the Human Rights Movement

More than twenty years have passed since the end of the cold war, and the time when people spoke in triumphal terms of the global ...

Summer 2014 (28.2) Review

Climate Matters: Ethics in a Warming World by John Broome

DALE JAMIESON This book greatly contributes to our attempts to meet the challenge of climate change and to answer the difficult questions that it raises.